Journal of Psychiatry Depression & Anxiety Category: Clinical Type: Perspective
The Medical Monopoly on Assisted Suicide
*Corresponding Author:
Jasper DoomenSchool Of Law, Open University, Heerlen, Netherlands
Tel:+31 718872901,
Email:jasperdoomen@yahoo.com
Received Date: Jan 26, 2018 Accepted Date: Mar 13, 2018 Published Date: Mar 27, 2018
Abstract
INTRODUCTION
• The physician must hold the conviction that the request by the patient was voluntary and well-considered
• The physician must hold the conviction that the patient’s suffering was lasting and unbearable; has informed the patient about the situation he was in and about his prospects
• The physician and the patient hold the conviction that there was no other reasonable solution for the situation he was in
• The physician has consulted at least one other, independent physician who has seen the patient and has given his written opinion on the requirements of due care, referred to in parts a-d
• The physician has terminated a life or assisted in a suicide with due care
Similar laws as those which apply in the Netherlands have been adopted in Belgium and Luxembourg. In both countries, just as in the Netherlands, doctors are exclusively allowed to euthanize; in addition, they have to adhere to strict criteria, which do not differ significantly from those that apply in the Netherlands. An important respect in which these three countries differ from others that allow euthanasia is that euthanasia on non-terminally ill patients is legal. With respect to assisted suicide, by contrast, there are important differences between Belgium and The Netherlands. The Belgian law does not provide criteria under which circumstances it would be allowed, from which it may be inferred that it is not allowed, but the issue has raised doubts and debate [1].
The number of euthanasia requests in The Netherlands has increased, the official reports having risen from 3316 cases in 2010 to 6091 in 2016. The vast majority of these requests have a somatic cause; a psychiatric reason was reported in 1% or fewer of the cases in each year [2]. A complicating factor is that in these cases, various symptoms converge: “Psychiatric patients do not only suffer from psychological symptoms, but also from general and specific physical and/or psychosomatic symptoms” [3]. Belgium, too, shows an increase in psychiatric euthanasia cases [4].
A known proponent of a perspective in which the right of self-determination is not decisive is the Belgian philosopher Herman de Dijn, who states: “The euthanasia act displays a profound opposition in our society, a struggle between conceptions of man and ideas about ethics that cannot be resolved by having everyone act in accordance with his or her own ideas. According to its opponents, the euthanasia act conveys a dangerous message: That certain lives are no longer worthwhile” [5]. This is not the proper place to extensively evaluate the arguments for the various positions. I will instead focus on the individual’s confrontation with his suffering, in order to ascertain to what extent the current Dutch legislation meets the demand that this suffering should be terminated. What is said here may also be of interest for readers who do not live in the Netherlands, for the theme that is discussed here is not particular to a specific country.
An evaluation of the legislation
‘Unbearable suffering’ may be interpreted broadly, covering both pain and (inter alia) “increasing dependence, an ever greater loss of dignity or the prospect of a gruesome death” [9]. Yet the government does not go so far as to deem the prospect of suffering lasting and unbearable, inter alia as ‘lasting’ and ‘unbearable’ are indivisibly linked [10]: “The mere prospect of suffering, irrespective of whether this will result from pain, loss of dignity or fear of an undignified death, cannot, in light of the above, be characterized as lasting and unbearable suffering” [10]. It becomes apparent from the evaluation that the fact that precisely that prospect is oftentimes the motive behind requests for euthanasia constitutes an important problem: “If one examines the reasons why people make a request to be euthanized, pain appears to be a factor in only a small number of requests. In actuality, what drives the request is almost always the loss of dignity that is to be expected” [11].
If this is correct, it is justified to say that the present legislation is not adequate to realize the desired goal. The problems will possibly increase with the impending population ageing. Research shows that a growing number of elderly people imagine themselves requesting euthanasia or having a suicide pill available [12]. The introduction of such a pill is, however, at least for the foreseeable future, a politically sensitive issue. In any event, world-weariness is not a recognized criterion to allow euthanasia or medical assistance in ending one’s own life [13] and neither is a ‘finished life’ [14].
A reform in this respect is pleaded by, amongst others, those who support the citizens’ initiative finished life (‘Burgerinitiatief voltooid leven’) [15]. In the wake of this initiative, political party Democrats 66 has submitted the bill Dignified End of Life (‘Waardig Levenseinde’), but this only pertains to people of 75 years or older. If the pill is only made available to the elderly-leaving the issue of what the precise age limit should be -, no solution has been offered to young people who face the same problem. Their position remains outside the purview of the law. This subject matter particularly lends itself to a medical ethical reflection, since the questions to which the subject matter gives rise cannot be answered by the medical profession itself [16].
This became clear in a case in which a general practitioner was found guilty of having assisted the suicide of a patient because the main criteria for medically assisted suicide had not been met, namely, that there has to be (in accordance with was indicated above) ‘lasting and unbearable’ suffering; he was discharged, however, as the act, while principally punishable, did not merit a punishment in this case. As the Dutch Supreme Court expresses it: “The integral care which is to be provided by a general practitioner to patients […] may result in him being assigned with the task to alleviate the suffering of a patient which is not or not predominantly caused by a somatic or mental condition, but which is the consequence of the lack of a life perspective. Given, however, that that physician then enters into a domain that lies beyond his professional competence, he may not, in his capacity of medical professional, form a judgment regarding the unbearableness, lastingness and untreatableness of that suffering” [17].
The question is, then, what, if any, recourse may be available to an individual who is confronted with suffering that cannot be qualified in medical terms, i.e., a case where neither depression nor a physical illness is diagnosed. In cases of ‘existential suffering’ the Supreme Court commands that a physician “consult others who may be helpful in finding a meaningful fulfillment of one’s daily existence” [18]. Who these ‘others’ might be is not elucidated and this may differ from one case to the next, so that a problem of referral will ensue (should a priest, rabbi or humanistic counselor-to mention just a few possibilities-be approached?). More importantly, no solution is provided for someone for whom, in spite of the availability of such possible alternative support, no meaningful fulfillment can be found [19]. This is not to be taken as criticism of the Supreme Court; the possibility to provide adequate support in such cases simply does not exist at the moment. Steven Pleiter, director of the End-of-life Clinic (‘Levenseindekliniek’), expresses the problem as follows: We, too, face patients who ‘suffer from life’-that is what we call it-and who have become detached […]. We cannot aid these patients under the present standard, since it is based on the presence of medical suffering. At times, dire situations occur, in which elderly people gravely suffer from life. In my view a proper solution should be available in such cases. The present Euthanasia legislation does not offer such a solution [20].
Towards a solution
In order to accommodate people whose suffering is not covered by the Termination of Life on Request and Assisted Suicide Act it is necessary to change article 294, section 2, of the Dutch Penal Code. This article penalizes, as was pointed out above, assisted suicide; only physicians who observe the demands specified in the Termination of Life on Request and Assisted Suicide Act are exempted. In order to confront the problems while acknowledging that some cases do not concern medical issues, non-physicians should also be exempted from punishment. Certain precautions should obviously be in place; crucially, it must be clear that there is a genuine death wish. With this in mind, one may argue that a physician still has a role to play: “If physicians” professional expertise enables them to deal with the existential questions arising in connection with VE [Voluntary Euthanasia] and PAS [Physician-Assisted Suicide] based on suffering caused by illness or injury-as the conventional view presupposes that it does-it would be inconsistent to deny VE and PAS for persons in purely existential distress by claiming that physician’s professional expertise does not extend to existential questions” [21].
Young’s solution, to have both a physician and a non-medical, professional counsellor assess individual cases, may, since he argues that if consulting the latter does not change the outlook of the person requesting assisted suicide this should be allowed [22], be advisable. In any event, it must be borne in mind that assisted suicide is still suicide (killing oneself). It would be both peculiar and undesirable to penalize assisted suicide if suicide (or attempted suicide) is not [23].
CONCLUSION
REFERENCES
- Nys H (2017) A discussion of the legal rules on euthanasia in Belgium briefly compared with the rules in Luxembourg and The Netherlands. In: David Albert Jones, Chris Gastmans, Calum Mackellar (eds.). Euthanasia and Assisted Suicide, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, England. Pg no: 5-6.
- https://www.knmg.nl
- Verhofstadt M, Thienpont L, Peters GY (2017) When unbearable suffering incites psychiatric patients to request euthanasia: Qualitative study. Br J Psychiatry 211: 238-245.
- Lopez-Castroman J (2017) About the practice of psychiatric euthanasia: A commentary. BMC Medicine 15: 125.
- De Dijn H (2011) Euthanasie: een cultuurfilosofische analyse. Ethische Perspectieven, Zoetermeer, Pg no: 71-87.
- Parliamentary Documents: House of Representatives (1993/1994), Pg no: 1: 4-5.
- Articles 293 and 294 of the Dutch Criminal Code.
- Parliamentary Documents: House of Representatives (1993/1994), Pg no: 1: 5.
- Parliamentary Documents: House of Representatives (1999/2000), Pg no: 6: 70.
- Parliamentary Documents: House of Representatives (1999/2000), Pg no: 6: 60.
- Parliamentary Documents: House of Representatives (2013/2014), Pg no: 8: 13.
- Buiting H, Deeg D, Knol D, Ziegelmann J, Pasman R, et al. (2013) Opvattingen van ouderen over levensbeë Huisarts Wet 56: 102-105.
- Parliamentary Documents: House of Representatives (2007/2008), Pg no: 3: 4-6.
- Parliamentary Documents: House of Representatives (1999/2000), Pg no: 6: 30-60.
- Parliamentary Documents: House of Representatives (2013/2014), Pg no: 8: 3.
- Bozzaro C (2015) Der Leidensbegriff im medizinischen Kontext: Ein Problemaufriss am Beispiel der tiefen palliativen Sedierung am Lebensende. Ethik in der Medizin 27: 93-106.
- Dutch Supreme Court (2002) 167: 2-8.
- Dutch Supreme Court (2002) 167: 5.
- Parker M (2012) Words and reasons: Psychiatry and assisted suicide. Aust N Z J Psychiatry 46: 80-83.
- Parliamentary Documents: House of Representatives (2013/2014), Pg no: 8: 9.
- Varelius J (2012) Medical expertise, existential suffering and ending life. J Med Ethics 40: 104-107.
- Young R (2014) ‘Existential suffering’ and voluntary medically assisted dying. J Med Ethics 40: 108-109.
- Macdonald M (1986) The secularization of suicide in England, 1660-1800. Past Present 111: 50-110.
Citation:Doomen J (2018) The Medical Monopoly on Assisted Suicide. J Psychiatry Depress Anxiety 4: 014.
Copyright: © 2018 Jasper Doomen, et al. This is an open-access article distributed under the terms of the Creative Commons Attribution License, which permits unrestricted use, distribution, and reproduction in any medium, provided the original author and source are credited.
